One Step Forward, Two Steps Back: a Charter Analysis of s.39 of Nova Scotia’s Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act Jacquelyn Shaw BSc, MSc, LLB, LLM (cand) Dalhousie University, Halifax, Canada
in light of disadvantages aff ecting psychiatric patients, I ask if
Abstract
rmative action, under s.15(2) of the Charter,
immunizing it from challenge. If not, does s.39 violate the equality
Nova Scotia’s recently updated Involuntary Psychiatric
guarantee of s.15(1), in its treatment of patients? Finally, I examine
Treatment Act signifi cantly updated mental health law in the
whether any infringement may be upheld as a policy decision
province in many respects. However, s.39 of the Act deviates
from this record in that it contains a clause that permits overriding the competent prior wishes of involuntarily committed psychiatric patients. This is problematic
D o e s s . 3 9 d raw a d i s t i n c t i o n b a s e d o n
because it displaces established Canadian common law and
a n e n u m e ra t e d o r a n a l o g o u s g r o u n d ?
legislation on advance directives for psychiatric patients but not other patients, suggesting possible discrimination
A long history of exclusion, shame, fear, segregation, and
The paper explores whether s.39 might survive challenge
mistreatment has been associated with mental illness. Under,
under s.15 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,
s.39 patients detained involuntarily due to mental illness may be
rmative action program under s.15(2) of
treated with mind-altering pharmaceuticals against their express
the Charter or as an overriding societal concern under s.1
wishes, made earlier, while competent. While some may claim such
treatment to be benefi cent and aimed at furthering the patient’s best interests, in reality, such forced treatment seems to have more
Ke y wo r d s : non-consensual treatment; treatment
in common with historical mistreatment, because it suggests that
refusal; advance directive; discrimination.
these patients’ wishes are not worthy of respect and that their legal rights are trivial. Th
is does not seem in keeping with the concepts
In 2005, Nova Scotia updated its mental health legislation of equality and human dignity central to the Charter.
with the Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act1 (‘IPTA’), a long-awaited improvement over earlier legislation that termed
Section 15(1) of the Charter states: “Every individual is equal before
psychiatric patients ‘lunatics’ or ‘the insane.’2 While IPTA no longer
and under the law and has the right to the equal protection and
uses disrespectful language, it remains problematic in another
equal benefi t of the law without discrimination and, in particular,
without discrimination based on .mental or physical disability.”12 In Law v. Canada, the purpose of s.15(1) of the Charter was found
IPTA’s s.39 empowers a substitute decision-maker to make
treatment decisions for an involuntarily committed psychiatric
.to prevent the violation of essential human dignity
patient3 using patients’ prior capable informed expressed wishes,
and freedom through the imposition of disadvantage,
unless doing so endangers the patient’s (or others’) “physical or
stereotyping, political or social prejudice, and to promote
mental health or safety”, whereupon “best interests” are substituted.4
a society in which all persons enjoy equal recognition at
ese words harbour radical negative eff ects: imposing treatment
law as human beings or as members of Canadian society,
despite capable prior wishes displaces Canada’s common law5 and
equally capable and equally deserving of concern, respect
legislation governing advance directives.6 Requiring only mentally
but not physically ill persons7 to have medical decisions imposed upon them seems intuitively unacceptable and suggests blatant
In turn, s.15(1)’s purpose is to identify discrimination (against
discrimination.8 Mentally ill persons have endured a long history
of discrimination, inconsistent with modern Charter values. It is disappointing to see this same dynamic within IPTA,9 one of
…a distinction, whether intentional or not, but based on
Canada’s most recent provincial mental health statutes.
grounds relating to personal characteristics of an individual or group, which has the eff ect of imposing burdens,
is paper argues that IPTA s.39 violates the Canadian Charter of
obligations or disadvantages on such individuals or groups,
Rights and Freedoms’10 s.15(1) equality guarantee. First, applying
not imposed on others, or which withholds or limits access
the vision of substantive equality elucidated in R. v. Kapp,11 I
to opportunities, benefi ts and advantages available to other
explore whether s.39 creates a distinction under s.15(1). Next,
2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health (ISSN: 1916-2405)
IPTA s.39 satisfi es the threshold criteria for a s.15 Charter
action, as it does not fi t the typical format. Usually in affi
action, a legal disadvantage, lack of benefi t or exclusion is conferred
and reveals evidence suggesting (a) a distinction or diff erential
on a relatively privileged group (e.g., white people), to confer
treatment of one group compared with another, (b) in which
needed advantages on a less privileged group (e.g., Aboriginals).26
one group receives greater benefi ts, legal protection or other
Section 39 confers a disadvantage on a less privileged group and
advantage, without justifi cation. Section 39 permits overriding
re-labels this as an ‘advantage’ to it. A similar argument failed
prior wishes in involuntary psychiatric patients but not patients
in R. v. Music Explosion, Ltd.,27 where a restrictive bylaw28 was
without mental illness, but suff ering from physical illness.15 In
claimed as a s.15(2) program “for the benefi t of the special needs
both groups, patients have competent prior wishes, but in only one
e Appeal Court, however, held that such
a restriction was not a conferral of special benefi ts but simply a
on the enumerated ground of mental disability, which creates lesser
legal protection for these individuals, attracting s.15’s attention.
of psychiatric patients to make their own treatment decisions may not qualify as a ‘special ameliorative program’. Kapp also stressed
I s s . 3 9 a n a m e l i o ra t i ve p r o g ra m
the importance that an ameliorative purpose be more than a “shield
u n d e r s . 1 5 ( 2 ) o f t h e C h a r t e r ?
to protect a program or activity which is.discriminatory.”31 Th
must be a genuine nexus between the claimed goal and the law’s form and implementation:
Charter ss. 15(1) and 15 (2) must work together, to promote
cient to declare that the object of a program is
an overall “vision of substantive equality.”16 Upon fi nding a
to help a disadvantaged group if in fact the ameliorative
distinction, attention shift s to s.15(2), asking if the diff erential
remedy is not directed to the cause of the disadvantage.
treatment “has as its object the amelioration of conditions of
There must be unity .among the elements of the program,
disadvantaged individuals or groups”, allowing it to escape being
[suggesting] that the remedy.is rationally related to the
ruled discriminatory. “Any law, program or activity” may constitute
cause of the disadvantage.23 (Emphasis added).
an ameliorative program so IPTA s.39 may qualify.
Many psychiatric patients are competent to choose their
Is s.39 an ameliorative program under s.15(2) for redressing
own treatment, contradicting societal myths of their global
incompetence and the seeming foolishness33 of their choices. Th
not violate the s.15 equality guarantee if the government can
unchallenged societal myths refl ect stereotypes and stigmatization34
demonstrate that: (1) the program has an ameliorative or remedial
of diff erence, aff ecting psychiatric patients’ in and beyond the
purpose; and (2) the program targets a disadvantaged group
ey generate disadvantages35 in employment, housing,
identifi ed by the enumerated or analogous grounds.”17 Th
fi nancial credit, and social participation, causing increased poverty,
determining s.39’s objectives, whether they are ameliorative, and
homelessness,36 addictions37 and criminalization,38 which in
whether any amelioration favours disadvantaged groups.
mental healthcare left little doubt that people with mental illnesses
Some may argue that s.39 has an ameliorative purpose. Th
experience disadvantage. Yet the real ‘cause’ of much of this
eory’ of psychiatric treatment18 claims many patients lack
disadvantage is oft en not illness itself, but false, over-generalized
insight and may later be grateful for treatment. Psychiatrist John
stereotypes that exclude patients from the community. Th
E. Gray (2000) argues that non-consensual treatment is necessary
while IPTA s.39 may reduce surface diff erences between mentally
to prevent greater patient suff ering, increased patient restraint
ill patients and others through enforced treatment, it leaves intact
or seclusion, longer detention (i.e., ‘warehousing’)19, poorer
and even perpetuates underlying societal myths about people with
prognoses for youth, negative impacts on staff , fellow patients
mental illnesses. Since IPTA s.39 does nothing to ameliorate these
and the therapeutic environment, greater costs20 and lost treatment
myths--the major cause of patients’ disadvantage-- a court may
opportunities due to ‘blocked beds.’21 Yet treatment refusals may
be an infrequent concern hardly warranting s.39’s existence: in one study only 7.2% of patients refused treatment, averaging just
D o e s s . 3 9 o f I P TA i n f r i n g e t h e s . 1 5 ( 1 )
13 days, while only 2% refused beyond 14 days. 22
C h a r t e r e q u a l i t y r i g h t ?
Some, including the ‘anti-psychiatry movement’23 which has legally empowered some competent psychiatric patients to
Diff erent treatment may not always constitute discrimination.
refuse unwanted treatment, counter that forced treatment is not
Substantive inequality does not always require identical
ameliorative. Patients may have valid reasons to reject treatment,
treatment between groups because, where relevant diff erences in
including undesirable side-eff ects, a preference for their own
group characteristics exist, “like treatment can generate serious
untreated thoughts and a right to make seemingly unwise choices.
inequality.”42 For s.39 to constitute discrimination requires
In addition, forced treatment may impair outcomes. Yet refusing
satisfying a two-part test: “(1) Does the law create a distinction
treatment may sometimes mean an untreated patient cannot be
based on an enumerated or analogous ground?43 and, (2) does
released into the community, needing long-term hospitalization,24
the distinction create a disadvantage by perpetuating prejudice
which some term “rotting with their rights on.”25
e second question requires examining four
contextual factors identifi ed in Law44 and Kapp: any pre-existing
Untreated mentally ill face grave disadvantages --possible direct
disadvantage aff ecting the group; any correspondence between the
suff ering from the illness, and negative societal attitudes-—
diff erent treatment and the group’s ‘reality;’ whether the impugned
deserving amelioration. Yet IPTA s.39 may not qualify as affi
law has an ameliorative purpose (or eff ect); and the nature of the
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 2 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
interest aff ected. Consider two of these factors in the context of
Are the means taken rationally connected to the objective sought?
If s.39’s objective involves ensuring treatment to optimize chances of release, the rational connection branch may also be met. A
e mentally ill have endured a long history of discrimination,
legislative attempt to redress marginalization of patients –ensuring
marginalization, and stigmatization. As noted, the lesser legal
treatment to remove stigmatizing symptoms—seems somewhat
protection accorded patients’ prior wishes under s.39 perpetuates
rationally connected to the goal, even if it cannot hope to eliminate
societal myths about psychiatric patients’ competence,45
infantilizing them and oversimplifying the more complex reality.46 It continues patterns wherein the opinions of the mentally ill
Anti-psychiatry’s supporters may disagree. Arguably, psychiatry
are deemed of lesser signifi cance and worth, suggesting a
has a long history of State suppression of eccentric, provocative (but
non-dangerous) people whose non-conformity, threatens public order, or those in power.58 Labelling and treating mental illness
e nature of the interest at stake in s.39 – the right to bodily
may be powerful tools for silencing, suppressing minority views
integrity and autonomy – is profoundly intimate, fundamental,
and enforcing conformity. Kate Millett (1990), a lawyer with bi-
and central to an individual’s sense of self. So important is it that,
polar disorder, also notes that psychiatry -- “the system that keeps
as noted in Fleming v. Reid, it is not only protected by the common
millions in line”59 — may have somewhat tenuous foundations:
law but also warrants constitutional protection under s.7 of the Charter as a right to security of the person, only to be denied
The entire construct of the “medical model” of “mental
according to the principles of fundamental justice. While the court
illness”—what is it but an analogy?.whereas in physical
in Fleming observed that the right is not absolute,48 but is subject
medicine there are verifi able psychological proofs.in
to overriding societal interests, it stated that bodily integrity and
mental illness alleged socially unacceptable behaviour is
autonomy deserve the “highest order” of protection.49 In this, “…
taken as a symptom, even as proof.Diagnosis is based on
few medical procedures can be more intrusive than the forcible
impressionistic evidence: conduct, deportment, and social
injection of powerful mind-altering drugs.oft en accompanied by
manner. Such evidence is frequently imputed. Furthermore,
severe and sometimes irreversible side-eff ects.”50
it may not even be experienced by the affl
instead may be observed [only] by others.60
Overall, the Law and Kapp factors suggest that s.39’s diff erential treatment perpetuates prejudice and denies psychiatric patients’
Psychiatry is a fi eld in some chaos: the scientifi c connection
s.15(1) ‘equality under the law’, suggesting that s.39 discriminates,
between mind and brain remains unclear61 and even explaining the
biological basis of the healthy human mind poses challenges. Does any competent patient possess autonomy in a medical decision,
C a n s . 3 9 o f I P TA b e s ave d b y s . 1 o f
or is such freedom illusory?62 Uncertainties abound:63 psychiatric
t h e C h a r t e r ?
diagnoses may vary and feigned illness may go undetected.64Medications65 also raise doubts regarding effi
Legislation may be saved as a “reasonable limit, prescribed by
eff ects.66 Physical side eff ects among older anti-psychotic drugs
law in a free and democratic society”51: a public policy choice,
include stigmatizing neurological symptoms. Th
refl ecting overriding societal interests, under s.1 of the Charter.
Haldol may risk lethal cardiac arrhythmias.67 Such side-eff ects
Analysis follows the four-step Oakes test below.
give patients valid reasons to consider refusing these older, but still used, drugs.68 While newer (‘atypical’) anti-psychotics exhibit
Is there a pressing and substantial objective? Section 39’s purpose
cacy and lack these side-eff ects, they possess other
seems directed at ensuring that patients receive medical treatment
eff ects. Although cardiac rhythms are not aff ected, signifi cant
and are released rather than warehoused.53 Some feel this goal
weight gain,69 metabolic changes and possible diabetes may pose
has been frustrated by lawyers more concerned with clients’ civil
cardiovascular risks to be weighed against benefi ts. Yet despite such
liberties than with patient well-being and potential. Herschel
doubts, s.39 may still demonstrate a suffi
Hardin (1993),54 former director of the British Columbia Civil
Liberties Association and father to a schizophrenia patient explains:55
Does the impugned legislation `minimally impair` the right infringed? Th
e legislature must tailor any rights intrusion, or
Far from respecting civil liberties, legal obstacles to
provide exceptions to it. IPTA’s requirement of the “least restrictive”
treatment limit or destroy the liberty of the person.Such
treatment70 suggests eff orts to tailor s.39’s intrusion.71 A “least
victims. cannot think for themselves or exercise any
restrictive” choice implies sometimes using physical restraints,
meaningful liberty.The opposition to involuntary committal
seclusion, persuasion and incentives72 to gain cooperation,
and treatment betrays a profound misunderstanding of
prevent harm and preserve the therapeutic environment. Yet if
the principle of civil liberties. Medication can. restore
any psychiatric treatment refusal progressively damages brain
[patients’] dignity, free will and the meaningful exercise of
and mind, or risks ‘mental harm to others’73 s.39 may subject
almost any competent patient to unwanted medication. Th
seems inconsistent with tailoring. Moreover, the specifi c right
us in view of the human values at stake56 the objective of ensuring
infringed by s.39 seems inconsistent with minimal impairment.
involuntary treatment does seem ‘pressing and substantial.’57
While neither rights to liberty nor bodily integrity are absolute, both are important s.7 Charter rights, only to be infringed in
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 3 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
accordance with the principles of fundamental justice. Yet they
many dimensions to their lives, only one of which involves their
biomedical status. Biomedical assessments cannot canvas all of the values a person may treasure, which defi ne him personally.
Liberty and security of the person diff er in their sensitivity to
Some patients prefer their own unique mental processes, as
interference. It is easier to tailor intrusions on liberty. Th
‘Starson’ (2003) preferred his rapid thoughts, supporting his
be done spatially, limiting a person’s movements, activities or
research.88 Others enjoy the emotional highs,89 or fi nd meaning
interactions, or at the extreme, by restricting almost all activity,
and livelihoods using artistic states inaccessible in treatment.
using seclusion, chemical or physical restraints.74 Liberty intrusions may also be modifi ed temporally, by duration. Security of the
Emerging concepts such as ‘Mad Pride’ seek to reclaim and
person,75 however, is much more sensitive to interference, and
celebrate, rather than pathologize,90 mental diff erence. Th
cult to infringe in a tailored way. Bodily integrity either
diversity91 movement’ holds that healthy human neurological
is, or is not, entirely breached by intrusions. Temporal tailoring
function forms a continuum of (equally acceptable) ways of
of intrusions seems meaningless when even brief intrusions on
thinking, including conditions labelled as illness or disability.92
bodily integrity, as in unwanted sexual contact, may have profound
Mental diff erences may be a ‘way of life,’93 as is ‘deaf culture’ to
some. Some argue the true location of mental ‘disability’ may lie within mainstream society’s unconscious reactions to diff erence,
Bodily integrity and autonomy rights –the right to dictate what is
not in the person claimed to be diff erent.
done to one`s body, brain and mind --also seem of more central value than liberty, given the importance of a person’s physical
Accordingly, is s.39’s cost-benefi t ratio proportional to the goal’s
‘being’ to identity, self-determination and survival. Individuals
e answer will depend on the values of highest
express their unique personal identities through their bodies,76
priority—those less reasonable to sacrifi ce. Here, freedom from
via temporary adornment,77 or permanent body modifi cations,78
interference with a patient’s bodily integrity and autonomy are
liations and social status. A person’s
of higher priority than staff morale, and patients’ potential and
self-identity, memories and personality also exist in a specifi c body
e body is therefore central to a person’s identity
psychiatric patients’ full potential, rather than warehousing
them, while important, cannot support serious impositions on the sacrosanct Canadian value of security of the person.
us, while both liberty and security of the person are important,
e proportionality step of the Oakes’ test must fail, therefore.
security of the person seems both more fragile and more central
Accordingly, at trial, it seems highly likely that s.39 would fail on
to the person, warranting greater protection. Th
at least two Oakes test branches and could not be saved under s.1.
(i.e., most minimally impairing)80 option requires infringing liberty
However, what remedies a judge might impose, such as striking
over bodily integrity.81 Yet s. 39 adopts the opposite approach of
down s.39 or reading in certain requirements, must await an actual
infringing bodily integrity82 to promote patients’ liberty, so it fails
to minimally impair psychiatric patients’ equality rights, clearly failing this third Oakes’ branch. Co n c l u s i o n Is there proportionality between benefi ts and costs of the means chosen or objective sought? For certainty, the fi nal Oakes test
Non-consensual treatment of competent psychiatric patients ranks
branch will also be explored. Here, the means (s.39) allows
among the most controversial healthcare issues. Some regard it as
interference with the personal autonomy of involuntary psychiatric
a travesty for a patient not to be treated, if there is any chance of
patients, against their express, competent wishes. Th
a dependent and isolated group, vulnerable to coercion, possibly
with younger patients, who face a longer period of potential illness
confused by illness and sedation, who cannot easily air their views.
(or health), and who may forfeit opportunities to establish career
us further restricting these patients` choices require caution, to
paths and important social relationships due to illness. Th
preserve patient autonomy wherever possible.
thus a temptation to view constitutional rights (including legal equality) as of lesser practical importance than a patient’s mental
Bodily integrity warrants “the highest order of protection”83 in
law, so proportionality requires s.39’s goal to be of comparable or higher priority. Section 39 off ers some benefi ts: it reduces violence,
Some may see s.39 as a compassionate response to mental illness.
verbal abuse and stress to staff or other patients, and may reduce
Yet its disregard for involuntary patients’ legal rights perpetuates
the application of more severe liberty restraints, shorten hospital
damaging stereotypes about patients, such as that their competent
stays84 and lower costs.85 Yet s.39’s forced treatment is an overly
wishes are unworthy of respect. Such healthcare double standards
simplistic approach to psychiatric illness that may cause harmful
in the treatment of physically and mentally ill patients add to rather
side-eff ects and impair real treatment progress.86
than alleviate any burdens from mental illness.
Tragic as such lost potential may be, it may be a necessary sacrifi ce
is paper has asked whether IPTA s.39 could survive a s.15 Charter
challenge. Overall, it seems it may not. While s.39 may superfi cially
asymmetry between medical staff and patient imply a trust
ameliorate the most visible disadvantages of mental illness through
situation, requiring respect for patient choices. Also in a diverse,
required treatment, it thereby reinforces our society`s invisible
pluralistic society should the views of only one group --healthcare
barrier to inclusion: stigma. Overall, s.39 starkly denies the Charter
staff —determine the ‘best interests’ of all patients?87 Patients have
legal equality guarantee, infringing a right --bodily integrity and
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 4 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
autonomy—considered sacrosanct in Canadian health law, which
Hermann, D.H.J. (1994) Mental Health and Disability Law (Eagan,
warrants stronger legal protection than liberty. Th
unlikely to be saved by s.1of the Charter, due to failures in minimal
Hospitals Act, R.S.N.S. 1989, c.208. s. 54A
Incompetent Persons Act, R.S.N.S., 1989, c.218, s.2 (b). Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act, S.N.S., 2005, c.42 [‘ IPTA’]
Although IPTA updated many aspects of Nova Scotia’s mental
Kesey, K. (1962) One Flew Over the Cuckoo’s Nest (New York: Viking).
health legislation, s.39 is less than progressive. In contrast to
Kirby M. J. L. and Keon, W. J. (2006) Out of the Shadows at Last:
the ‘emergence from the shadows’ heralded for mental illness
Transforming Mental Health, Mental Illness and Addiction Services
this century, s.39 suggests a return to a more paternalistic era.
in Canada, Final Report of the Standing Committee on Social
Unchallenged, s.39 represents several steps backwards for
Aff airs, Science and Technology, May 2006 [‘the Kirby Report’]
psychiatric patients, compared with those in Canada`s physical
Kirk, T. and Bersoff , D. N. ‘How many procedural safeguards does it
take to get a psychiatrist to leave the light-bulb unchanged? A due process analysis of the MacArthur Treatment Competence Study,’ (1996) 2 Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 45-
R e f e r e n ce s : Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) [1999] 1
Law Society of British Columbia v. Andrews [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143 at
Appelbaum, P.S. (1994) Almost a Revolution: Mental Health Law and the Limits of Change (New York: Oxford University Press).
e delicate dance in Canadian mental health policy:
American Psychiatric Association, (2006) American Psychiatric
balancing equality rights, family rights and community rights,’
Association Practice Guidelines for the Treatment of Psychiatric
(2008) 3 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health 1 -5. Disorders: Compendium 2006, (Arlington, VA: American
Malette v. Shulman (1990), 72 O.R. (2d) 417, 67 D.L.R. (4th) 321 at
Bartlett, K.T. ‘Feminist legal methods’ (1990) 103 Harvard Law ReviewMental Health Act, C.C.S.M., c.M110 s.28(4)(b)(ii)
Metzger, E. and Friendman, R. “Prolongation of corrected QT interval
Bear, M.F., Connors, B.W. and Paradiso, M.A. (2001) Neuroscience:
and torsades de pointes cardiac arrhythmia associated with
Exploring the Brain, 3rd ed. (Lippincott, Williams & Wilkins:
intravenous haloperidol in the medically ill” (1993) 13 J. Clin. e Atlantic (30 September 1998) online
e Loony-Bin Trip (New York: Simon & Schuster).
at: www.theatlantic.com/doc/199809u/neurodiversity (accessed
Pothier, D. ‘Miles to go: some personal refl ections on the social
construction of disability’, Dalhousie Law Journal 526 -543.
e ethics of involuntary treatment: the [1982] position of
the Canadian Psychiatric Association’, (1982) 27 Can. J. PsychiatryR. v. Music Explosion, Ltd., (1990), 68 Man. R. (2d) 203 at para. 18.
R v Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103 at para 69-71, 77
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution R. v. Laba, [1994] S.C.J. No. 106 at para 79-91. Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K.), 1982,
Ray, O. and Ksir, C. (2004) Drugs, Society and Human Behaviour 10th
Canadian Mental Health Association, ‘Informed consent to treatment’
e Queen (1985), 21 C.C.C. (3d) 116 (Man. Q.B.).
online at: www.cmha.ca/bins/print_page.asp?cid=5-33-
e Queen (1985), 20 C.C.C. (3d) 196 (B.C.S.C.), aff ’d
174&lang=1 (accessed 3 March 2009).
Canadian Mental Health Association,‘Stigma and Mental illness’
Saner, E. “It`s not a disease, it`s a way of life,” Th
online at www.cmha.ca (accessed 3 March 2009)
online at: www.guardian.co.uk/society/2007/aug07/ health.
Canadian Mental Health Association (British Columbia),
‘Criminalization of Mental Illness’ online at: www.cmha.bc.ca/
Schizophrenia Society of Canada, ‘Schizophrenia Society disappointed
fi les/2-criminalization.pdf (accessed 27 September 2009)
with Supreme Court decision` and sample ‘Letter to the Editor’
Chadwick, R. and Levitt, M. ‘Genetic technology: a threat to deafness’
for members, online at: www.schizophrenia.ca (accessed 11
(1998) 1 Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy 209-215. Consent to Treatment and HealthCare Directives Act, R.S.P.E.I. 1988,
Slobogin, C. (2006) Minding Justice: Laws that Deprive People with Mental Disability of Life and Liberty (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Corbiere v. Canada (Minister of Indian and Northern Aff airs), [1999]
Starson v Swayze. [2003] S.C.J. No. 33 at para 76. e Astonishing Hypothesis (Charles Scribner’s Sons:
Sullivan, G., Burnam A. and Koegel, P. ‘Pathways to homelessness
among the mentally ill,’ (2000) 35 Soc. Psychiatry Psychiatr. Fleming v. Reid, [1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 31
Gillett, G. ‘Intention, autonomy and brain events,’ (2009) 23 Bioethics
Tallis, R. “Why blame me? It was all my brain’s fault: the dubious
e Times (24 October 2007) online: www.
Gordon, H. ‘Treatment Act divides mental health advocates` Nova
timesonline.co.uk/tol/comment/columnists/guest_contributors/
News Net (4 November 2005) online at http: http://novnewsnet.
Tisdale, J.E., Kambe, J.C. , Chow, M.S. and N.S. Yeston, “Eff ect of
Gray, J.E., Shone, M.A. and Liddle, P.F. (2000) Canadian Mental Health
haloperidol on ventricular fi brillation threshold in pigs” (1991)
Law and Policy (Toronto: Butterworths).
69 Pharmacol. Toxicol. 327-9.
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 5 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
Torrey, E.F. (1997) Out of the Shadows: Confronting America’s Mental Illness Crisis, (Toronto: J. Wiley & Sons, Inc.)
(a) in accordance with the patient’s prior capable informed
Weiner, B.A. and Wettstein, R.M. (1993) Legal Issues in Mental Health
(b) In the absence of awareness of a prior capable informed
Weisstub, D.N. (1990) Enquiry on Mental Competency: Final Reportexpressed wish, in accordance with what the substitute
decision-maker believes to be in the patient’s best interest.
Wildeman, S. (2008-9), ‘Mental Disability Law’ (course), Dalhousie
A second example, Prince Edward Island’s Consent to Treatment and HealthCare Directives Act, R.S.P.E.I. 1988, c.C-17.2, ss.20 and 24 state:
20. (1) Every person over the age of sixteen years who is capable
E n d n o t e s Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act, S.N.S., 2005, c.42 [‘ IPTA’]
(a) stipulate treatment, procedures, or medication that
Incompetent Persons Act, R.S.N.S., 1989, c.218, s.2 (b).
the maker authorizes or refuses to consent to, or directs
Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act, s.3(m): an ‘involuntary
to be discontinued, in the circumstances set out in the
patient’ means “a patient who is admitted to a psychiatric
facility pursuant to a declaration of involuntary admission.” A
(b) stipulate circumstances in which the maker shall be
psychiatrist can make a declaration of involuntary admission
permitted to die a natural death, receiving only
palliative care intended to reduce pain and suff ering;
(b) the person is in need of the psychiatric treatment
(d) specify an event or condition upon which the directive
(c) the person, as a result of the mental disorder,
(e) make any other direction concerning the health care
(i) is threatening or attempting to cause serious
harm to himself or herself or has recently done so,
24. (1) A decision contained in a directive shall be as eff ective
has recently caused serious harm to himself or herself,
as if made by the maker when the maker had capacity to make
is seriously harming or is threatening serious harm
towards another person or has recently done so,
Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para.60.noted that the
right to bodily integrity and autonomy is not absolute. Th
(ii) is likely to suff er serious physical impairment or
there may be limited circumstances where competent psychiatric
patients’ autonomy may validly be curtailed, for example, in
(d) the person requires psychiatric treatment in a psychiatric
emergency mental health situations, where a patient must be
facility and is not suitable for inpatient admission as a
temporarily chemically restrained using sedative drugs. Th
seems reasonable since individual rights are never absolute but
(e) as a result of the mental disorder, the person does not
must be weighed against other rights, or those of other parties or
have the capacity to make admission and treatment
the community. For instance, in physical healthcare, autonomy
rights of competent patients may also be curtailed in limited
Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act, s. 39: Th
circumstances, such as where a patient has been diagnosed with
decision-maker shall make the decision in relation to specifi ed
a serious communicable disease (e.g., multiple-drug resistant
psychiatric treatment and other related medical treatment
tuberculosis) that presents a serious public health risk. It should
(a) In accordance with the patient’s prior capable informed
be noted that the patients aff ected by s.39 of IPTA are not at
large in the community or able to leave the hospital at will. All
(b) in the absence of awareness of a prior capable informed
are involuntarily hospitalized and thus pose no danger to public
expressed wish or if following the patient’s prior capable
informed expressed with would endanger the physical
IPTA s.39 is not entirely unique in Canada in its attempts to
or mental health or safety of the patient or another
override the competent advance wishes of psychiatric patients.
person, in accordance with what the substitute decision-
For example, Manitoba’s Mental Health Act, C.C.S.M., c.M110
maker believes to be in the patient’s best interests.
s.28(4)(b)(ii) accomplishes much the same end. Section 28(4)
Malette v. Shulman (1990), 72 O.R. (2d) 417, 67 D.L.R. (4th) 321
at para. 18 and 24: “Under the doctrine [of informed consent],
A person who makes treatment decisions on a[n incompetent]
no medical procedure may be undertaken without the patient`s
patient’s behalf under subsection (1) shall do so
consent.” and: “A doctor is not free to disregard a patient`s
(a) in accordance with the patient’s wishes, if the person knows
advance instructions any more than he would be free to disregard
that the patient expressed such wishes when apparently
instructions given at the time of the emergency.” Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 31: “Th
(b) in accordance with what the person believes to be the
what shall, or shall not, be done with one’s own body, and to be
free from non-consensual medical treatment, is a right deeply
(i) the person has no knowledge of the patient’s expressed
(ii) following the patient’s expressed wishes would
Hospitals Act, R.S.N.S. 1989, c.208. s. 54A states (for example):
endanger the physical or mental health or the safety
e substitute decision-maker shall make the decision in relation
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 6 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
While this paper focus specifi cally on IPTA s.39, many of the
treatment. J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and P.F. Liddle, Canadian
arguments may be applicable to other provincial legislation that
Mental Health Law and Policy (Toronto: Butterworths, 2000) at
attempts to override psychiatric patients’ competent wishes in
10-12. P.S. Appelbaum also discusses the ‘common-sense model’
in which he argues psychiatrists and judiciary in practice oft en
While IPTA is in the minority in its overriding of psychiatric
ignore the law, preferring involuntary committal and treatment
patients’ competent wishes, it is not entirely alone in so doing
is, he claims, priorizes (presumed) patient suff ering
in Canada. For example, the Manitoba’s Mental Health Act s.
over legal rights. P.S. Appelbaum, Almost a Revolution: Mental
28(4)(b)(ii) permits an almost identical situation, overriding
Health Law and the Limits of Change (New York: Oxford
the patient’s expressed wishes (made while competent) with
best interests where following such wishes would “endanger
ere may is a belief by some that the entire purpose of
the physical or mental health or safety of the patient or another
hospitalization is to treat and discharge psychiatric patients,
person.” In addition, British Columbia’s Mental Health Act s.31(1)
rather than simply detaining them long-term to protect them
may override competent patient wishes by deeming patient
or the public, termed ‘warehousing.’ J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and
consent to treatment have been given, on the basis of detention;
P.F. Liddle, Canadian Mental Health Law and Policy (Toronto:
and New Brunswick’s Mental Health Act s.8.11(2) may override
Butterworths, 2000) at 208; C. Slobogin, Minding Justice: Laws
competent advance directives if they are not reliable, not current,
that Deprive People with Mental Disability of Life and Liberty
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006) at 222.
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution
Psychiatrist C.H. Cahn described the situation as a trade-off
Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K.), 1982,
or quid pro quo, in which he claimed restriction of a patient`s
liberty could only be justifi ed by giving a patient (eff ective,
non-harmful) treatment in return. C.H. Cahn, ‘Th
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution
involuntary treatment: the [1982] position of the Canadian
Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K.), 1982,
Psychiatric Association’, (1982) 27 Can. J. Psychiatry 67 at 70.
Countering this is the view that psychiatric hospitalization is
Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) [1999]
itself a form of treatment, or a vital part of the healing process for
e hospital environment off ers supportive
Law Society of British Columbia v. Andrews [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143
human relationships, monitoring and interaction, improved
hygiene, shelter, nutritional and educational benefi ts, freedom
While no comparator group may be perfect, and others could
from illicit street drugs, physical abuse, hypothermia, criminal
perhaps have been selected, patients suff ering physical illness
justice system involvement and other dangers, compared to
seemed the most useful comparator group for the purposes of this
the potentially isolated and impoverished circumstances of
paper. Ideally, in a s.15 Charter analysis, the comparators should
homelessness, to which a patient may have been subject prior
be very similar in all respects except for their legal treatment,
which is the focus of the comparison. Choosing the physically ill
From longer hospitalizations, added nursing and administrative
seemed to appropriately emphasize the role of illness in creating
the undeservedly unequal legal situation on which this paper
21 J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and P.F. Liddle, Canadian Mental
focuses. Alternatively, it might have been possible to compare,
Health Law and Policy (Toronto: Butterworths, 2000) at 202-7;
for instance, the mentally ill detained under s.39 with the group
B.A.Weiner and R.M. Wettstein, Legal Issues in Mental Health
composed of non-mentally ill persons detained criminally. While
Care (New York: Plenum Press, 1993) at 120, 124.
some might think it appropriate to thereby place the emphasis
T. Kirk and D.N. Bersoff , How many procedural safeguards does
on detention and loss of liberty, this appeared less useful due to
it take to get a psychiatrist to leave the light-bulb unchanged: a
the very diff erent purposes detention may express in these two
due process analysis of the MacArthur Treatment Competence
groups: in the former, protection (of patient and potentially
Study, (1996) 2 Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 45 at 46.
public), and in the latter, public protection but also punishment
e anti-psychiatry movement formed the basis for the novel
and the expression of societal disapprobation. Th
One Flew Over the Cuckoo’s Nest, a novel which harshly critiqued
aspect of justly deserved punishment and moral disapprobation
psychiatry’s treatment of involuntarily committed psychiatric
patients; K. Kesey, One Flew Over the Cuckoo’s Nest (New York:
mentally ill detained involuntarily as to make it an inappropriate
comparator, because in that case there genuinely appears to be a
ere are, of course, similarities between involuntary psychiatric
non-discriminatory reason for any diff erent treatment.
committal and criminal incarceration: both share “loss of
R. v. Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 16.
liberty, separation from family and friends, stigma of being
R. v. Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 41.
institutionalized and reliance on the state to satisfy basic needs.”
ank-you theory’ has been attributed to psychiatrist
D.H.J. Hermann, Mental Health and Disability Law (Eagan, MN:
Alan Stone by T.Kirk and D.N. Bersoff , ‘How many procedural
West Publishing, 1994) at 193. However, there are also important
safeguards does it take to get a psychiatrist to leave the light-bulb
diff erences, such as that the purpose underlying psychiatric
unchanged? A due process analysis of the MacArthur Treatment
detention is not punitive or deterrent.
Competence Study,’ (1996) 2 Psychology, Public Policy, and Law
i.e., in full possession and awareness of their legal rights, yet
45 at 46. Some related concepts are of note. Th
because of these legal rights supporting treatment refusal, unable
perspective’ on mental illness is promoted by some as an antidote
to access their seeming ‘right’ to their full potential in life and
to civil libertarian eff orts to legally empower psychiatric patients
a place in society. D. Treff ert, quoted in C. Slobogin, Minding
to contest involuntary committal and resist unwanted medical
Justice: Laws that Deprive People with Mental Disability of Life
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 7 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health and Liberty (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006)
found to be disadvantaged to advance an argument of affi
action. As the Court noted in Corbiere v. Canada (Minister of
As noted by the Court in Law, “Legislation which seeks to
Indian and Northern Aff airs), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 203 at para.70-72:
ameliorate disadvantage may not off end s.15(1) of the Charter
to qualify as ameliorative of disadvantage, it is not necessary for
even if it excludes certain other individuals or groups.However,
all individuals members of a generally `disadvantaged` group
this is only the case where the group excluded .is more advantaged
to suff er disadvantage, or to the same degree; confi rmed in R. v.
in a relative sense than those the legislation seeks to assist.”
Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 59.
(Emphasis added). Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and
Individuals with psychiatric diagnoses are overrepresented among
Immigration) [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497 at para. 72
the homeless, totalling 20-25% of the homeless population. G.
R. v. Music Explosion, Ltd., (1990), 68 Man. R. (2d) 203 at para.
Sullivan, A. Burnam and P. Koegel, ‘Pathways to homelessness
18. Yet the Court noted that in two diff erent cases, sections
among the mentally ill,’ (2000) 35 Soc. Psychiatry Psychiatr.
of the Criminal Code and Young Off enders Act were upheld as
Epidemiol. 444 at 444. In contrast, individuals with schizophrenia,
rmative action programs under s.15(2): Re Rebic and Th
bipolar disorder and major depression account for only 1%, 2%
Queen (1985), 20 C.C.C. (3d) 196 (B.C.S.C.), aff ’d (1986), 28
and 5% of the population respectively; M.F. Bear, B.W. Connors
C.C.C. (3d) 154 (B.C.C.A.) and Re M and Th
and M.A. Paradiso, Neuroscience: Exploring the Brain, 3rd ed.
21 C.C.C. (3d) 116 (Man. Q.B.). Both cases upheld diff erences
(Lippincott, Williams & Wilkins: New York, 2001) at 673, 674,
in incarceration periodsas ameliorative of the special needs of
certain classes of off enders: mentally ill off enders found not
37 More than 50% of people with psychiatric disorders also have
guilty by reason of insanity (then detained under a Lieutenant-
substance abuse problems; Canadian Mental Health Association
Governor’s Warrant), and youth serving time while awaiting trial,
(British Columbia), ‘Criminalization of Mental Illness’ online at:
respectively. In both cases, the impugned law seemed rationally
www.cmha.bc.ca/fi les/2-criminalization.pdf
related to identifi ed unique needs of the parties aff ected: the need
One estimate is that 15-40% of inmates in Canada’s criminal
for long-term separation of dangerous mentally ill patients from
justice system have a mental illness; Canadian Mental Health
society for their own and others’ safety, and the need for greater
Association (British Columbia), ‘Criminalization of Mental
leniency with youthful off enders. In contrast, in Music Explosion,
Illness’ online at: www.cmha.bc.ca/fi les/2-criminalization.pdf
the impugned bylaw’s attention to younger teenagers did not
e Kirby Report into Canadian mental healthcare found
seem to refl ect a rational ameliorative purpose related to the
widespread stigma and discrimination against mentally ill
youths’ abilities or special needs, appearing almost arbitrary. Th
people in employment, housing, social opportunities and even
circumstances of s.39’s involuntarily hospitalized but competent
healthcare, with debilitating eff ects on lives and recovery. One
mentally ill treatment-refusers more closely resembles the
contributor stated: “Some patients struggle with poverty so
fact pattern in Music Explosion, with its seemingly arbitrary
grinding and housing so appalling, it would challenge the sanity
restriction of these patients’ rights to have their competent
of even the strongest among us.” Another added: “Individual
recovery from mental health [problems] is impossible when
Limiting younger teenagers’ use of a musical ‘amusement device’
struggling with the consequences of poverty alongside stigma
R. v. Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 53.
Wilbert J. Keon, Out of the Shadows at Last: Transforming Mental R. v. Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 54
Health, Mental Illness and Addiction Services in Canada, Final
R. v. Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 46.
Report of the Standing Committee on Social Aff airs, Science and
R. v. Kapp [2008] S.C.J. No. 42 at para. 48, quoting Manitoba Rice
Technology, May 2006 at7, 8 [‘the Kirby Report’]
Farmers v Human Rights Commission (Man.), [1985] M.J. No.
Numerous scholars have discussed the social construction of
disability (or diff erence) and the question of where precisely such
33 As the court in Fleming v. Reid said: “Th
disability (or diff erence) is located: in the individual claimed to
treatment] must be honoured. regardless of how ill-advised the
be diff erent or in a society unwilling to accept or accommodate
patient’s decision may appear to others.” Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4
that diff erence? D. Pothier, ‘Miles to go: some personal refl ections
O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 32-33.Also in Starson v Swayze. [2003] S.C.J.
on the social construction of disability’, Dalhousie Law Journal
No. 33 at para 76, the Supreme Court stated: “Th
526 at 530-1; R. Chadwick and M. Levitt, ‘Genetic technology: a
to be foolish is not unimportant; the right voluntarily to assume
threat to deafness’ (1998) 1 Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy
209 at 210; and K.T. Bartlett ‘Feminist legal methods’ (1990) 103
Harvard Law Review 829 at 843. Mental illness has similarly been
Stigma involves “negative attitudes or beliefs that are held about
claimed to be a social construction located not so much in the
people who are perceived as diff erent”; since they are oft en semi-
aff ected individual, but in the society in which that person lives,
which is unwilling to accept and accommodate their mental
Organization (WHO) stated in 2001 that stigma was “the single
illness and the diff erences it represents.
most important barrier” faced by people with mental illnesses.
An absurd analogy might be an attempt to eliminate racism
Reported by the Canadian Mental Health Association, ‘Stigma
by superfi cially ‘whitewashing’ people of diff erent ethnicities
and Mental illness’ accessed online at www.cmha.ca As one
without addressing and rooting out the underlying myths, fears
contributor noted: “We attach no blame to someone who
and stereotypes fueling (oft en semi-conscious) racist attitudes.
develops a physical illness, but when it comes to mental illness,
Andrews , McIntyre J. quoted that “.there is no greater
people experience discrimination on a daily basis.”
inequality than the equal treatment of un-equals;” Law Society all individuals with mental illness may experience
of British Columbia v. Andrews [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143 at para 26. Th
disadvantage, it is not necessary that all mentally ill individuals be
view that like treatment does not accord with true, substantive
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 8 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
equality was also re-iterated by the Court in R. v. Kapp [2008]
Including possible patient suff ering, loss of liberty and exclusion
due to stigma and involuntary committal, and lost human
Law v.Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) [1999]
e urgent societal goals of reducing homelessness, poverty,
addictions and criminalization of the mentally ill may also be
D.N. Weisstub, whose Enquiry on Mental Competency: Final
indirectly assisted, if treatment lets patients gain insight, acquire
e Enquiry, 1990) at 116, was cited in evidence
healthy lifestyle patterns and establish career, educational and
by the Supreme Court in Starson v Swayze. [2003] S.C.J. No.
social networks for life in the community. Out of the Shadows: Confronting America’s Mental
with lack of capacity, which occurs to an even greater extent Illness Crisis, (Toronto: J. Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1997) at 172-3
when involuntary commitment is involved, has deep historical
e Loony-Bin Trip (New York: Simon & Schuster,
roots, and…attitudes and beliefs have been slow to change. For
this reason, it is particularly important that autonomy and self- e Loony-Bin Trip (New York: Simon & Schuster,
determination be given priority when assessing individuals in this
According to current mainstream scientifi c consensus, the ‘mind’
ere is in general no such thing as global competence or
is a product of interactions between the neurons of the brain
incompetence. In some patients, competence may fl uctuate over
e Astonishing Hypothesis (Charles
time, or be present for some decisions but not others. However,
Scribner’s Sons: New York, 1994) at 7.
overall, many mentally ill patients are competent either all or at
Numerous authors have questioned whether human beings in
least part of the time for all or at least some decisions.
general can be said to possess meaningful free will, autonomy and
erefore, individuals whose s.7 Charter rights to life, liberty or
free choice in our decisions; F. Crick, Th
security of the person are to be infringed must receive procedural
(Charles Scribner’s Sons: New York, 1994) at 10, 171, 267-8;
fairness entitlements, such as a right to an impartial hearing, a
R.Tallis, “Why blame me? It was all my brain’s fault: the dubious
e Times (24 October 2007) online: www.
timesonline.co.uk/tol/comment/columnists/guest_contributors/
protections for security of the person under s.39 (e.g., a Board
article2726643.ehtml. In the specifi c context of healthcare
hearing at the mental hospital, where a substitute decision-maker
decisions made by competent patients, Grant Gillett has explored
deliberates on the patient’s ‘best interests’). However, this may
the meaningfulness of informed consent in light of mental factors
not be enough. As discussed elsewhere, s.39 of IPTA has the
that appear to undermine truly free choice in healthcare (e.g.,
potential for a s.7 Charter challenge too, although this issue will
framing eff ects and other unconscious irrational forces directing
decisions). He concludes that the deliberation process is not just a
Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 60
facade, and that competent patients do in fact possess meaningful
Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 39
Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 40
by patients’ decision-making within (or in opposition to) the
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution
knowledge scaff olding provided by an informed mentor (the
Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K.), 1982,
healthcare provider or others); G. Gillett, ‘Intention, autonomy
and brain events,’ (2009) 23 Bioethics 330 at 336-7. R v Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103 at para 69-71, 77; and R. v. Laba,
63 While the lack of scientifi c understanding of psychiatric
[1994] S.C.J. No. 106 at para 79-91.
treatments may seem concerning, in physical illness, aft er
is conclusion is based on several factors: the s.2 subordination
safety assessments, certain medical treatments or drugs may be
of patient self-determination rights (respected only “where
routinely used, as Aspirin’s active ingredients once were, without
possible”) to treatment; the overriding eff ect of s.39 on prior
a full understanding of their mechanism of function.
wishes (opposing the usual trends in informed consent); the
J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and P.F. Liddle, Canadian Mental Health
Act’s title (the Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act); and
Law and Policy (Toronto: Butterworths, 2000) at 41.
the admission requirement under s.17(e) that, involuntary
Once termed neuroleptics, the older-style (fi rst-generation)
psychiatric patients lack competence.
anti-psychotic medications included drugs such as haloperidol
Out of the Shadows: Confronting America’s Mental
(Haldol), used to treat psychotic patients with various diagnoses.
Illness Crisis, (Toronto: J. Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1997) at 162.
ere are now also newer `atypical` (or second-generation)
anti-psychotic drugs, such as olanzepine (Zyprex). O. Ray and
has argued that competent patients` Charter liberty rights are
C. Ksir, Drugs, Society and Human Behaviour 10th ed. (Boston:
violated by allowing them to remain untreated; Schizophrenia
McGraw-Hill, 2004) at 225-7. However, the older fi rst-generation
Society of Canada, ‘Schizophrenia Society disappointed with
drugs still appear to be in use, as discussed infra.
Supreme Court decision` and sample ‘Letter to the Editor’ for
e older generation of anti-psychotics worked by blocking
members’ use, online at: www.schizophrenia.ca (dated 11 June
dopamine receptors, causing a similar clinical picture to
2003). I am indebted to Professor Sheila Wildeman for drawing
Parkinson’s disease, where a defi ciency of dopamine ant the
my attention to this article in her course ‘Mental Disability Law’
dopamine receptors is caused by reduced dopamine production
at Dalhousie University Law School. In this distorted view of
us as a result of the older anti-psychotic drugs,
liberty, untreated psychiatric patients are claimed to have no
some 20% of patients suff er Parkinsons-like motor side-eff ects,
meaningful liberty; E.F. Torrey, Out of the Shadows: Confronting
including for 2% of patients, tardive dyskinesia, a motor
America’s Mental Illness Crisis, (Toronto: J. Wiley & Sons, Inc.,
disorder featuring writhing facial movements, drooling, etc. Th
chance of Parkinsons-like side eff ects may be reduced either by
JEMH · November 2009 · 4(2) | 9 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
administering a second (anti-cholinergic) drug to block motor
Mental Health Law and Policy (Toronto: Butterworths, 2000) at
side-eff ects, by carefully selecting an (older-style) anti-psychotic
196. However, this is a misconception: whether the unwanted
drug, or by using atypical anti-psychotic drugs, although the latter
drug therapy is oral or by injection, the eff ect remains the same:
possess other concerning side eff ects. O. Ray and C. Ksir, Drugs,
the drugs enter the person’s body and transit the blood brain
Society and Human Behaviour 10th ed. (Boston: McGraw-Hill,
barrier, potentially aff ecting the competent patient’s most
intimate thoughts in an unwanted manner. Th
67 American Psychiatric Association (APA), American
the route of administration, the patient’s right to bodily integrity
Psychiatric Association Practice Guidelines for the Treatment
has been violated, and to the same degree.
of Psychiatric Disorders: Compendium 2006, (Arlington, VA:
For example, no competent skin cancer patient, regardless of
American Psychiatric Association, 2006)) at 85; E. Metzger
how life-threatening or treatable their disease, is required to
and R. Friendman, “Prolongation of corrected QT interval
undergo treatment, on the justifi cation that the patient and
and torsades de pointes cardiac arrhythmia associated with
his potential can be saved, preventing family distress and later
intravenous haloperidol in the medically ill” (1993) 13 J. Clin. Psychopharmacol. 85-86; J.E. Tisdale, J.C. Kambe, M.S. Chow
physically ill is a well-recognized right at law and will ordinarily be
and N.S. Yeston, “Eff ect of haloperidol on ventricular fi brillation
respected to avoid legal liability for battery. Comparable respect
threshold in pigs” (1991) 69 Pharmacol. Toxicol. 327-9.
for competent wishes of the mentally ill is required in psychiatric
APA Practice Guidelines for 2006 identifi ed
care, in the interests of legal equality.
haloperidol as still the “anti-psychotic medication of fi rst
Fleming v. Reid,[1991] 4 O.R. (3d) 74 at para. 39.
choice,” American Psychiatric Association Practice Guidelines
Untreated patients’ stays may average twice as long, generating
for the Treatment of Psychiatric Disorders: Compendium 2006,
higher costs. J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and P.F. Liddle, Canadian
(Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association, 2006) at 85. Mental Health Law and Policy (Toronto: Butterworths, 2000) at
e delicate dance in Canadian mental health
204. Some treatment-refusers are hospitalized for much longer—
policy: balancing equality rights, family rights and community
ordered to spend a 12-month period in hospital, ‘Professor
rights,’ (2008) 3 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health 1 at 1.
Starson’ had been hospitalized for years by his trial date in
Involuntary Psychiatric Treatment Act, S.N.S., 2005, c.42, s. 2(c)
2003; Schizophrenia Society of Canada, ‘Schizophrenia Society
In addition, the s.39 override only applies to some mentally ill
disappointed with Supreme Court decision`, online at: www.
patients at certain times: those who risk harm to self or others.
schizophrenia.ca (dated 11 June 2003). Some never return to
For example, outdoor grounds privileges.
the community nor fulfi l their potential, although medication
Including an unjustifi ed fear of untreated patients)
Some argue that impositions on one`s physical autonomy (via
Gray argues that warehousing a treatment-refuser for two
forced psychiatric treatment) restrict not only physical liberty
years might cost $330,000, while a one-month treatment costs
but mental liberty as well. C. Slobogin, Minding Justice: Laws
only $15,000, followed by release. J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and
that Deprive People with Mental Disability of Life and Liberty
P.F. Liddle, Canadian Mental Health Law and Policy (Toronto:
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006) at 222.
Butterworths, 2000) at 206. Yet his estimate omits the need for
‘Security of the person’ will be used interchangeably here with
post-release community supports and medications. Hence the
the common law rights to bodily integrity and autonomy.
actual cost asymmetry remains unclear.
Including gender, age, racial and ethnic characteristics.
86 Professor Sheila Wildeman describes IPTA`s involuntary
For instance, clothing, hairstyling, jewellery and cosmetics.
treatment as a “combative approach to psychiatric therapy” that
Such as diet, exercise, surgical augmentation, and skin piercing
“polarizes the therapeutic relationship” and is counterproductive
to meaningful treatment; H. Gordon, ‘Treatment Act divides
Fleming noted that few intrusions are more extreme
mental health advocates` Nova News Net (4 November
than the legislatively enforced administration of mind-altering
2005) online at http: http://novnewsnet.ukings.ca/nova_
drugs, aff ecting this intimate body part.
news_3588_6825.html Studies show that treating patients against
As noted, the s.7 right to security of the person is only to be
their will generally results in poorer prognoses; C. Slobogin,
restricted in accordance with the principles of fundamental
Minding Justice: Laws that Deprive People with Mental Disability
justice. Yet s.39 of the IPTA appears to restrict security of the
of Life and Liberty (Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA,
person in discriminatory manner, which cannot be in accordance
with the principles of fundamental justice. Fundamental justice
e Canadian Medical Health Association states: “It cannot be
and discriminatory treatment are diametrically opposed in eff ect
assumed that medical treatment is the only or best option for
us s.39 seems unlikely to minimally impair the
individuals [with mental illnesses].” Canadian Mental Health
s.15 equality right because not only does s.39 completely impair
Association, ‘Informed consent to treatment’ online at: www.
a patient`s right to bodily integrity, but it does so on the basis
cmha.ca/bins/print_page.asp?cid=5-33-174&lang=1 (accessed
of values diametrically opposed to the principles of fundamental
Starson v Swayze. [2003] S.C.J. No. 33 at para. 46.
e mode of administration of unwanted medication is notOut of the Shadows: Confronting America’s Mental
relevant to whether or not a violation of bodily integrity and
Illness Crisis, (Toronto: J. Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1997) at 156.
autonomy has occurred. Gray suggests that since injections of
Again, I am grateful to Professor Sheila Wildeman and her course
medications are now rarely used in modern Canadian psychiatry,
‘Mental Disability Law’ at Dalhousie University Law School, for
this is acceptable because no force is being used against the
drawing my attention to this emerging trend, described in an
patient (presumably implying there is no violation of bodily
undated Toronto Star article by H. Henderson, entitled ‘Mad
integrity); J.E. Gray, M.A. Shone and P.F. Liddle, Canadian
Pride’, accessed online at: www.mindfreedom.org/mindfreedom/
2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
madpride/Toronto_d.shtml (accessed 30 January 2004).
online at: www.theatlantic.com/doc/199809u/neurodiversity
92 Maintaining and encouraging mental differences –
neurodiversity-- may be as important as preserving biodiversity, to ensure humanity`s future adaptability and survival: “Who can say what form of [neurological] wiring will prove best?” H. Blume, “Neurodiversity” Th
online at: www.theatlantic.com/doc/199809u/neurodiversity
E. Saner, “It`s not a disease, it`s a way of life,” Th
online at: www.guardian.co.uk/society/2007/aug07/ health. medicineandhealth
Acknowledgements: Th e author gratefully acknowledges the encouragement, inspiration and many helpful editing suggestions of Professor Jocelyn Downie of Dalhousie University Law School. She would also like to acknowledge with sincere appreciation many insights regarding psychiatric care and Canadian mental health law generally, gained while attending Professor Sheila Wildeman’s course ‘Mental Disability Law’, taught at Dalhousie University Law School in 2008-2009. Finally, she thanks Dalhousie’s Novel Tech Ethics for supporting her with a student award for presentation of the paper at the recent conference ‘Brain Matters: New Directions in Neuroethics,’ in Halifax, Nova Scotia, September 25-6, 2009. Academic, Professional and Financial Affi liations: Recipient, Canadian Institutes of Health Research (CIHR) Training Fellowship; Recipient, Student Trainee Award, ‘Brain Matters’ conference (Novel Tech Ethics, Dalhousie University). Funding recipient, Neuroethics Emerging Team, Dalhousie University. Funding recipient, Law Foundation of Nova Scotia.Competing Interests: None. Address for Correspondence: #28-1424 Seymour Street, Halifax, Nova Scotia, B3H 3M5 email: shawja@dal.ca 2009 Journal of Ethics in Mental Health
Ályktanir og áskoranir Aðalfundar Náttúruverndarsamtaka Austurlands, Egilsstöðum 14. apríl 2012 Dráp á friðuðum fuglum Að undanförnu hafa borist fréttir af því að verið sé að skjóta friðlýsta fugla. Þannig fannst nýverið dauður fálki á Mýrum í Hornafirði og voru 7 högl í hræinu. Að skjóta fálka er aldrei mistök. Fjórðungur fálka sem finnas
PREPARATION INSTRUCTIONS FOR COLONOSCOPY with SPLIT‐DOSE Movi‐Prep Do you have QUESTIONS or PROBLEMS completing the instructions? Call: 206‐242‐1300 Appointment date: ____________ Appointment time: ____________ Location: _____________ BEFORE the procedure: Arrange a ride: you will be given medicine that makes you relax and be sleepy,